CEPA eprint 2477

Making sense of non-sense in physics: The quantum koan

Bitbol M. (2014) Making sense of non-sense in physics: The quantum koan. In: Cappuccio M. & Froese T. (eds.) Enactive cognition at the edge of sense-making: Making sense of non-sense. Palgrave Macmillan, Houndmills: 61–80. Available at http://cepa.info/2477
Table of Contents
1 Introduction
2 Quantum enigmas and Buddhist therapy
3 Some quantum paradoxes: a deflationary approach
4 Looking for hidden meaning or confronting non-sense?
Relaxing the struggle for sense-making: a strategy to make sense of quantum theory
6 The Zen model: relaxation of sense-making as a way of life
7 Applying the Zen model to appease the quantum demand for representational sense-making
8 Conclusion
References
In scientific knowledge, meaning-ascription is usually identified with representation-making. But quantum physics challenges this view. It has consistently prevented scientists from providing a unified narrative about the world, thus making them fear falling into non-sense. Few of them have accepted restricting their attention to the apparently nonsensical surface of micro-phenomena, together with the efficient predictive formalism of quantum theory, rather than telling a tale about putative depths behind phenomena. One wonders, then, whether taking representations as a paradigm of sense-making, even in cases like quantum physics where this looks problematic, is connected to a bias of Western culture. An alternative cultural stance, that of Zen Buddhism, is found to accommodate more easily the kind of non-representational epistemology that makes sense of quantum physics.[Note 1]
1 Introduction
Quantum paradoxes can be treated as a welcome occasion to test the basic hypothesis of enaction, far beyond its usual sphere of immediate situated know-how. In order to see how this can be done, let me remind the reader of some elementary facts about the enactive paradigm. Enaction was originally presented as a middle-way between realism and idealism, between the belief that the form of knowledge bears the mark imposed by a pre-structured world (that it “represents” the latter somehow) and the opposite belief that the world is nothing more than a projection of the cognitive system. At first sight, this middle-way involves a coupling between subject and environment, out of which their structures co-emerge as knowledge and world. But it was clear from the outset (Varela et al., 1991, chapter 11) that such a relational and dualist characterization is (paradoxically) nothing more than a tentative representation of the reason why one should suspend the use of the concept of a “representation of the world” in our understanding of cognition. More rigorously (and less dualistically), one may then understand enaction as a conception that treats knowledge as a transactional process of sense- making which takes place below the level of representations. This sense- making, in turn, is construed as the operation of associating a procedure of adaptive action with as many classes of environmental configurations as possible. In other terms, when an organism ascribes meaning to some such configuration, this usually does not imply that it holds a picture of the deep recesses of the world, say of its minute constituents and their mutual relations. It only signifies that the organism knows what to do next, when it meets (or triggers) certain co-emerging patterns in its surroundings.
However, the straightforward anti-representationalist and possibly anti-realist upshot of enaction has been challenged. Some authors have claimed that, notwithstanding the relevance of anti-representationalism for elementary cases of evolutionary fitness, it lacks universality (Clark, 1997). The concept of representation, indeed, looks increasingly indispensable to account for cognitive processes when they get closer to the high-level of full-blown scientific knowledge. In the latter case, meaning-ascription is identified with representation-making. As soon as this is accepted, the resistance of a certain domain of investigation to the activity of representation-making can easily be taken for a case of irruption of non-sense: not being able to establish a unique and coherent picture of the field of exploration is said to entail a loss of meaning. Yet, this strong connection between representation and sense-making at advanced stages of knowledge could well turn out to be:
1. The expression of a misunderstanding about what a representation does in scientific knowledge. Indeed, one can fail to get a (unified and faithful) representation of the world, without renouncing representation of parts of it as this or that, according to certain models (Van Fraassen, 2008).
2. A mere effect of perspective due to the fact that these foremost stages of knowledge are implicitly likened to classical science, taken as a norm.
In contrast, one can easily figure out an even more advanced stage of knowledge in which: (i) the ability to provide a unified picture of the field of investigation is challenged, and retrospectively seen as a particular case adapted to our standard macroscopic Umwelt (ii) the reason for this collapse of coherent representations is understood from an epistemological standpoint; and (iii) despite the lack of any all-encompassing representation, an abstract mathematical structure guides our (technological) activities more efficiently than ever, possibly assisted by a set of clumsy, incomplete, ancillary pictures. In this new situation, the hierarchical ordering of (a) action-related sense-making and (b) elaborate unified representations would be turned upside-down once again. Instead of construing representation as an accomplished phase of knowledge beyond mere behavioral adaptation, one would see it as a more or less optional instrument that is sometimes used in highly advanced forms of enactive fitness. As for mathematical formalisms, they would no longer be taken for a structural image of the actual world, but, rather, understood as a systematic inventory of our most precise possibilities of action (along with Jean Piaget’s genetic psychology or Andrew Pickering’s neo-pragmatism).
Now, this kind of post-classical conception of knowledge is precisely instantiated by quantum physics. In quantum physics, (i) it was soon suspected (especially by Niels Bohr) that a fully coherent all-encompassing representation might well be out of reach. At most, one can provide a mathematical scheme that has the mental function of a “representation” without being a representation of the world (Schrödinger, 1951, p. 40; Bitbol, 1996a, p. 29); (ii) the reason for this apparent limitation was soon understood to be the contextuality of micro-properties; and (iii) it was soon realized that this was absolutely no hindrance to the efficiency of the mathematical scheme of the theory. But, for nearly a century, there has been continuous struggle against these unexpected and unwanted conclusions. Many scientists felt that lacking a unified and consistent narrative about the world is tantamount to falling into non-sense. And they desperately attempted to overcome what they saw as a failure. Very few researchers tried the opposite strategy that consists in pushing Bohr’s approach to its ultimate consequences, thus making sense of the apparent non-sense of the collapse of representations, and looking for a new process of sense-making below (or beyond) the level of representations. Very few of them decided to explore the apparently nonsensical surface of micro-phenomena, and to make sense of their being limited to this surface, rather than trying desperately to tell a tale about the elusive depths hidden behind phenomena. Since taking representations as a paradigm of sense-making might be connected to a bias of our Western culture, I will confront it with a Zen Buddhist perspective. After all, the highest achievement of the Zen path might easily be understood as a recognition of global meaninglessness while making sense of it.
2 Quantum enigmas and Buddhist therapy
If there is any benefit to be found in comparing quantum theory and Buddhism, microscopic physics and the Way of awakening, this benefit certainly does not consist of over-determining thought by favoring a specific thesis concerning the world and its hypothetical depths (Capra, 1975/2010).[Note 2] It should, on the contrary, make it possible to free scientific thought from its chains of inherited forms. It should invite us to unlearn the habitual aim of seeking to represent some sort of “reality” hidden behind appearances: an aim which might well be illusory, and is the source of most of the quantum “paradoxes” (Bitbol, 1996b, 2003, 2010). Besides, as Varela et al. (1991) explained, Buddhism can play a considerable role in going beyond enaction as a theoretical scheme, towards a mode of life in which its stance about cognition becomes a matter of course. Then, in remarkable conformity with the original spirit of Buddhism, the sole relevance of a comparative approach to quantum theory and connected issues in epistemology is that conferred by its therapeutic power. Its task is to lend support to the philosophical endeavor, which, following the teaching of Wittgenstein, does not aim at explaining; or at answering questions; or at seeking facts, putting forward conjectures, or unearthing the foundations of knowledge (Lock, 1992). This endeavor aims solely at “pacifying” the compulsive drive to access the “ultimate nature of that which is”; to treat archetypal questions of this order as so many “pathologies” or “mental cramps”; and, finally, to let things be “the way they are”, after having learned to live (and to talk) with them as they will (Wittgenstein, 1953/1968).
One may, of course, ask why support of this sort is necessary. Is philosophy (in the Wittgensteinian sense) not quite capable of carrying out by itself its mission of putting to rest the metaphysical flights of imagination which sometimes guide, sometimes mislead scientific thought? Is not Buddhism, and all the more so the Zen version, which is so succinct that it appears enigmatic and cryptic, after all a stranger to the constitutive dialogue between Western science and philosophy ever since their inception? This would be to forget that the work of philosophy, whether it aims at systematic construction or the critique of systems, is not solely a question of explicit intelligence. It is (or should be) the work of human persons who are not content to put forward positive assertions, but who adopt an existential posture, from which their major intellectual positions are often derived. Large-scale theoretical options, such as empiricism or materialism, can thus be rightly attributed to attitudes which are gener-ally essentially tacit, even more so than simple presuppositions (Van Fraassen, 2002). Doctrinal pontifications have time and again proven to be fashioned, unbeknown to themselves, by ways of life.
Certainly, these forms of philosophical life cover a whole range of modes of being-in-the-world, ranging from the most embodied and engaged to the most abstract and distant; but the balance between these two poles is strongly biased in favor of the second, because of a background set of distancing and “naturalizing” values typical of our Western culture (Descola, 2008). This explains in large part the obstinate resistance of many thinkers when they are faced with the radical changes in perspective that would be necessary to dissolve questions which are manifestly badly posed, and which have led the inquiry concerning the foundations of quantum physics into an impasse. Indeed, these changes in perspective would amount precisely to a re-investment of what is concrete and manifest in the daily practice of laboratory life (and therefore easily accounted for by the enactive paradigm of sensorimotor sense-making), after a long interlude during which the audacious productions of an intelligence bent on world-building held sway. It is this same cultural preference which explains why the critical and therapeutic strategies of a few philosophers have overwhelmingly met with reactions of rejection (or proposals to “supersede” them) from their own community. An illustration of this is provided by the severely negative reactions of Russell and Popper to Wittgenstein’s “second philosophy” (Lock, 1992). By contrast, a current of thought such as Zen – which is an open invitation to work on the embodiment of gestures and conducts (Herrigel, 1948/1993), which issues from the very practice of sobering up conceptually and of “letting things be”, which has no aim other than being an accessory to a radical lightening of the existential load – offers the possibility of a profound change in the subsoil of unconscious taken-for-granted attitudes on which philosophical endeavors are built. The scale of priorities risks being turned upside-down; the critical and therapeutical branch of philosophy may gain a new legitimacy from its synergy with a mode of being which accomplishes it in practice; and the quest to dissolve a certain number of (false) problems in quantum physics may be strengthened by leaning on a program of philosophical treatment.
3 Some quantum paradoxes: a deflationary approach
It will now suffice to show, by several case studies, how this new synergy actually works in practice; we will find that the majority of the “weird paradoxes” of quantum physics dissolve away and no longer appear “weird”, once we have untied the knot of cultural prejudices which held them excessively tight.
There is a premise which conditions all these case studies. It concerns the evaluation of the epistemological status of quantum theories. What are these theories, what do they succeed in doing, and what do we have a right to ask of them? Do they offer an explanation, or at least a description unequaled in its precision, of subatomic processes? Have they made it possible to elucidate the intimate mechanisms of chemical phenomena and nuclear transformations? Have they penetrated further into the fundamental nature of things than classical theories, such as the mechanics of Galileo and Newton, thermodynamics or electromagnetism, have ever managed to do before? The great misunderstanding which runs through the debates on quantum physics stems from the fact that most of the time it is thought that this is the way things must be: that the three questions listed above must be construed as so many positive assertions. The belief of Western science in a telos here claims its due. However, once one accepts that, a whole cascade of disturbing conclusions burst forth. The world which is supposedly “revealed” by quantum mechanics has an appearance as unexpected and ludicrous as Alice’s Wonderland recounted by Lewis Carroll. And in this case it would seem that all that can be done is to accept the weirdness.
As is well-known, one of the first surprises is the wave-particle duality, this strange association between extension and point localization, between continuity and discontinuity, which is supposed to describe the “nature” of the new entities that are sometimes called “quantons” (Lévy-Leblond and Balibar, 1984). Einstein, the first scientist to have imagined entities of this sort (concerning electromagnetic radiation), was unable to hide his perplexity on this subject: “Is it possible to reconcile the quanta of energy on one hand, and the Huygens principle on the other? Appearances go against it, but God seems to have found the trick of it” (Einstein, 1989). It may be added that, although our spontaneous intuition cannot digest this amalgam between the discontinuous and the continuous, between quanta and the “Huygens principle” for wave interference, we ourselves seem to have found a “trick” which has the reputation of being able to combine them and thus to “enter into the mind of God”. The mathematical formalism of Hilbert does indeed make it possible to establish a connection both with a continuous geometry (by means of the concept of the spatial amplitude of a probability or a “wave function”) and with an algebra of discontinuity (by means of the scheme of quantization). But does this formal derivation really suffice to reconcile the two contradictory concepts, or does it just amount to rejecting them both (setting them back-to-back) and substituting something quite different in their place?
A second surprising finding is the problem of measurement A famous way of telling the story so as to bring out its dramatic implications is the paradox of Schrödinger’s cat (Schrödinger, 1935/1983). The most succinct account of this paradox plays on the contradiction between the state of the cat as described and as concretely occurring. Quantum mechanics (so it is said) describes the cat subjected to Schrödinger’s infernal machine[Note 3] as being in a superposed state of being both alive and dead. However, in actual practice it is found that the cat is found to be either alive or dead. Here, the (supposed) quantum description of the cat does not accord with what one sees of it. Dozens of solutions have been proposed to get around this difficulty. One of them consists of taking the quantum “description” literally, and to suppose that each of the two terms in the superposition represents a separate “possible world”: in one of these worlds the cat really is alive (and the inhabitants of this world see the cat alive), and in the other world the cat is dead (and the inhabitants find it dead). However, the way out that is currently dominant (called “decoherence”) amounts to refusing to confront the problem according to the standard formulation, and to changing the formulation in a way that is so subtle that many scientists are unaware of the sleight of hand: instead of a problem of compatibility between conjunction and disjunction, between a plurality of possibilities and the uniqueness of what actually exists, the problem that is resolved is a problem of connection between two forms of the calculation of probabilities (Lyre, 1999; Bitbol, 2009).
A third disturbing finding was formulated for the first time by Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen (1935/1983). Even though the aim of these authors was to demonstrate the “incompleteness” of quantum mechanics (its incapacity to describe all the “elements of reality” attached to physical systems), what posterity has retained from their reflections is quite different (d’Espagnat, 1994). The enigma which remains bears on the explanation of the strange “EPR correlations” predicted by the “entangled states” of quantum mechanics. How is one to understand the strict correlation between the values of observables measured on pairs of particles which were initially in contact but which are now situated at arbitrarily large distances from each other? Briefly, the only two explanatory frameworks which are plausible are (a) common causes and (b) reciprocal causal influence. But each of these two explanatory possibilities encounters insurmountable obstacles in quantum physics. Considering that the origin of the correlations lies in common causes amounts to asserting that they are inscribed in the properties of the particles, and that these properties have been fixed ever since the initial moment when the particles were contiguous. However, this option (called local hidden variables) is excluded by Bell’s theorem (Bell, 1987).[Note 4] The other hypothesis, that of reciprocal causal influences with an arbitrarily large speed (including larger than the speed of light), has indeed been modeled and tested experimentally in recent years (Suarez, 2000); but it has been refuted and must therefore be rejected in its turn. How is it possible to extricate oneself from this impasse? Two extreme options remain available. On the basis of the presupposition of “scientific realism” (according to which quantum theory describes the properties of things as they really are, including their inseparability), the only way out is to adopt an ontological holism. According to this doctrine, space and time are only emergent deployments of an “implicate order” (Bohm, 1984), which is pre-spatial and pre-temporal; and the two distant particles are in truth distinct manifestations of one and the same universal entity. Their correlation no longer has to be explained by any sort of transmission, from the past to the present or from a present here to a present over there, but simply by a statement of identity. At the opposite extreme, according to the most radical of the anti-realist options, there is simply no need to “explain” an instantaneous correlation at a distance, for the good and simple reason that the latter has no intrinsic existence. The correlation only ever sees the day relatively to mechanical and electromagnetic devices apt to “provide evidence for it”. Now, that can only come about when the information concerning one of the correlated properties has had a sufficient time (at least the time that would be taken by a light signal) to rejoin the region of space where the information concerning the other property is available (Smerlak and Rovelli, 2007; Bitbol, 1983). No “non-local influence” need be invoked in this case.
The fourth disturbing finding covers, in fact, a whole network of clues that point towards a conception of physical theory that is not descriptive or representational, but, rather, purely predictive and informational (Brukner and Zeilinger, 2009). A large number of experiments (some of which have actually been carried out, others which are pure thought- experiments) make it pretty much unthinkable that one could describe processes which are supposed to have happened before the actual act of their detection or observation; and this forces one to trust only the information drawn from such an act by basing oneself on previous knowledge of the configuration of the experimental setup as a whole. I will mention just two of these experiments: “measurements without interaction” and “delayed-choice experiments” (Scully and Drühl, 1982; Elitzur et al., 2003). In the first sort of experiment, information derived from an absence of interaction between the object and an intermediate part of the instrument has exactly the same consequences as those that would result from their actual interaction (Elitzur and Vaidman, 1993). That is enough to make one think that what counts in a quantum experiment is not the detail of the hypothetical processes which may be supposed to occur between the preparation and the final detection but, rather, the informational content that the whole structure of the apparatus confers on the event of detection. Indeed, in some spectacular experiments with “delayed choice”, the object interacts with an elementary measuring agent (for example, a photon), but its so-called “state” depends on decisions that can be made millions of years later concerning the arrangement of the device which makes it possible to collect the photon. Unless one imagines that certain influences can go backwards in time (as certain physicists have been led to propose (Wheeler, 1978)), it must be recognized that what may be carelessly called “the state of an object” expresses nothing other than the information made available by the observational apparatus which gives access to it after the moment when all the decisions concerning the apparatus have been taken.
4 Looking for hidden meaning or confronting non-sense?
Each of these paradoxical situations can lead one (and many physicists have not hesitated to take the step) to consider that there is something quite extraordinary in the occult nooks and crannies of the world; something that quantum descriptions give an oblique glimpse of, but that neither our language nor our imagination can properly grasp, and that only mathematics makes it possible to circumscribe. Nevertheless, the very same situations can also be interpreted in a diametrically opposite fashion, as we have hinted at during our presentation of them. Once they are re-considered in the most intellectually economical fashion, all these supposed “paradoxes” converge towards the possibility that quantum theory is nothing more than an ingenious but purely formal way of anticipating experimental information; that it does not offer an incomplete and cryptic revelation of an invisible and ineffable reality, but only a method for orienting oneself with respect to that which shows itself and is said; that, instead of penetrating further into the recondite depths of matter than any previous theories have managed to do, quantum mechanics is, rather, a systematic inventory of its surface. For every one of these “paradoxes”, without exception, can be immediately dissolved (in the absence of the means and, above all, of any real motivation for resolving them) as soon as one renounces the application to quantum mechanics of the descriptive, representationalist, “realist” conception of physical theories. Accepting the “non-sense” of the collapse of representations here allows us to make better sense of a physical theory. Let us take up again the first two “paradoxes”, bringing out the sketch of a dissolution which has already been suggested. The dissolution of the latter two paradoxes has already been sufficiently indicated.
Assigning a double nature, as wave and as particle, to the objects called “quantons” is a biased, over-determined and prejudiced way of expressing a phenomenon which does not a priori impose either an ontology of waves or an ontology of particles. The phenomenon in question is the distribution of a large number of punctual events according to a pattern which is isomorphic to that which would be produced by the interference of two waves or the diffraction of a single plane wave passing through a hole. Bohr himself already criticized treating this sort of phenomenon in ontological terms when he replaced the assertion of a wave-particle duality by that of a complementarity of the images of a wave and a particle. Each image is only relevant, according to Bohr, with respect to a particular experimental context; and the contexts which render these two images appropriate are partially exclusive of each other. But that is not all. It can be shown in a quite general way that any theory capable of accounting for phenomena concerning mutually exclusive contexts predicts distributions which will have a wave-like appearance (Destouches-Février, 1951); that is, distributions where everything happens as though we are dealing with waves even though there are no waves at all. In other words, far from manifesting the absolute wave-like properties of microscopic entities, the interference behavior of quantum phenomena could be the eloquent sign of their epistemic relativity; far from bearing witness to the deep nature of things, the pseudo-wavelike effects could well represent one of the most salient marks of the superficial, interfacial character of the phenomena that quantum mechanics makes it possible to anticipate.
The case of the paradox of Schrödinger’s cat can be dealt with in even more summary fashion, if only one accepts once again following the lead given by Bohr. The apparent contradiction here derives from the repeated use of the term “state”, which actually has two quite different meanings. The superposed quantum “state” of the cat does not fit with the “state” that is manifest and observable. This apparent conflict disappears as soon as we recognize that the quantum “state”, far from indicating what the cat actually is, only makes it possible to estimate the chances one has of seeing it in a certain way; that, far from corresponding to a “state” in the full and proper sense of the term, the quantum “state” vector is nothing other than a symbolic instrument making it possible to evaluate the probability of finding the cat in one or other of its two biological states. Indeed, no one has ever required that a probabilistic evaluation should reveal in advance the actual outcome (in the full and proper sense of the term) of the event in question; in the same way, no one should hope to reveal or to engender the actual observed state of the cat merely on the basis of the quantum probabilities. The only non- conventional aspect of quantum theory is the peculiar (non-additive and interferential) structure of its calculation of probabilities, which is quite different from the classical calculation, because it is adapted to the contextuality of microscopic phenomena (Bitbol, 1998). The only remaining problem thus consists of linking up (at least approximately) this non-classical structure of probabilities with the classical additive structure which is valid for the mutually exclusive events observed in the laboratory. This problem is solved, as we have already indicated, by the theories of decoherence.
Relaxing the struggle for sense-making: a strategy to make sense of quantum theory
If we wish to express the lesson of these reflections in a deliberately provocative way, we might remark that quantum mechanics is better understood, and in a way that avoids posing logically insoluble problems, by admitting that it reveals rigorously nothing about the alleged intimate nature of its objects. After all, if quantum mechanics is considered as a generalized process of evaluating probabilities, there is no more reason for it to reveal the nature of its objects than the classical theory of probabilities has of revealing the nature of objects to which it is commonly applied, such as dice, or roulette tables, or fluctuations in the financial market, or the clients of an insurance company. Just like the theory of probabilities, quantum mechanics is grafted onto the outside layer of events that it aims at anticipating – without penetrating into a hypothetical “interior”. Even more than the theory of probabilities, quantum mechanics rests on the surface of things, because what it anticipates are not even actual events that will come about by themselves, but merely potential phenomena which require a particular experimental setup in order to occur (Bohr wrote that these phenomena are defined by such an experimental setup). And that is still not all. Not only does quantum theory reveal no intimate nature of things beyond the phenomena, but its success and its fruitfulness are easily explained by the fact that it incorporates in its very structure the limits to the exploration of phenomena. Its success and its fruitfulness come from the fact that it does not even allow any meaning to the belief that there might be something deeper to understand behind the superficial screen which is its own domain of validity. Heisenberg’s indeterminacy relations can thus be considered as the expression of a limit to any possible knowledge of the dynamic variables of elementary particles. But these relations are at the same time a powerful tool of theoretical exploration which has made it possible to predict, among other things, the bandwidth of rays of electromagnetic emission, the lifetime of radioactive nuclei, and a number of striking effects of quantum field theory (such as virtual particles, the Casimir forces, etc.). Here, the limit to knowledge is not a matter of a provisional obstacle, but determines the very form of what is to be known. Relaxing the usual struggle towards representational sense-making turns out to be a good strategy to make sense of the efficiency of quantum mechanics.
Indeed, not only is quantum mechanics the superficial prediction of superficial phenomena, but its redoubling of superficiality is what accounts for its remarkable vocation for universality. If quantum theory is, above all, a general procedure for anticipating on a probabilistic mode the replies to experimental solicitations, or more precisely for anticipating replies which correspond to the type and the order of these solicitations, then it ought to be generally applicable to any domain whatever that is solicited. Now, this does indeed turn out to be the case, which reinforces the initial “deflationist” interpretations. The recent generalization of quantum theory, which is applicable to many domains in the human sciences (Bruza et al., 2009a; Bitbol, 2009) running from decision theory to semantics by way of the psychology of perception, is a remarkable illustration of this. It does not matter who or what responds (human beings or things), the probabilistic structure of the responses is the same. From this restricted point of view, a set of human beings making choices which depend on the options that are presented to them, and on the order of the decisions to be taken, behave exactly like a set of electrons on which one evaluates several incompatible observables (Zwirn, 2009). A set of speakers who have to decide on the meaning of a polysemic word, according to the propositional contexts, thus behaves exactly like a set of microscopic particles which violate the Bell inequalities (Bruza et al., 2009b). There is nothing shocking about the fact that it should be so, and it implies absolutely nothing about any community at the level of their profound being between electrons and humans; there is only a formal isomorphism in their situation and their “surface” reactions to being solicited.
To recapitulate, the conception of quantum mechanics as being doubly “superficial” (both superficially phenomenal and superficially probabilistic) makes it possible to dissolve away what are alleged to be the major paradoxes of this theory; to explain a large part of its effectiveness; and to promote its universality. As if this were not enough, one can add that this conception also maintains a remarkable degree of notional and mathematical simplicity, which contrasts strongly with the ever-increasing sophistication of those ideas which aim at saving a “realist” interpretation of quantum physics. Why, under these conditions, is this conception not more widely accepted? Why does it so often find itself opposed by the indignant reactions of certain physicists who reproach it with “betraying the ideal of science”, of “breaking the great dream of knowledge” (Stengers, 1997), of being unacceptable or even “scandalous” (Thom, 1993)? Why, even when indignation is absent, does the exposition of the minimalist conception of quantum theory give rise to a resigned silence which manifestly expresses a profound disappointment? There is no doubt that it is because, as we have suspected since our introduction, we are dealing with a breach of several contracts at the level of a whole civilization. One of these is a fairly recent contract, which, from the 16th century onwards, has instigated a collusion between the desire for a metaphysical breakthrough upheld by the clerks and the need for technological perfectionism of the craftsmen (Scheler, 1926/1993). Another is a very ancient contract, which has made it an obligation to seek a principle of understanding appearances in the inmost depths of things (Schrödinger, 1954). If scientific progress does not help our gaze to penetrate to the very heart of material bodies, and to definitively guarantee technological effectiveness by laying bare their secret, what is the point of it? If the progress of knowledge amounts merely to a kaleidoscopic deployment of the phenomenal skin of things, instead of opening up a vision of their very flesh and marrow, does it not seem in vain? It is all very well to recall that all the entities which, in the history of science, were pompously dignified at the time by the title of “realities behind appearances” have turned out to be themselves a matter of (1) other appearances (or phenomena) revealed by a new approach, postponing the revelation of what Goethe called the “Urphänomen” (Seamon and Zajonc, 1998) to an indefinitely remote utopia; or (2) mathematical idealities which express some invariants of the phenomena reconstructed by the intelligence. This simple reminder is not enough. The “dream of reason” pursues its course; this same dream that Kant upheld at the beginning of his quest, before discarding it in his critical philosophy: the dream of managing to grasp by thought a “representation of things as they are” (Kant, 1770/2004).
The fact that this dream survives in spite of the obstacles, that it seems deaf to everything which can sap its foundations (in particular in the field of quantum physics), confirms the suspicion we have already formulated: we are not dealing here with intellectual convictions based on solid rational argument, but, rather, with civilizational postures which have been internalized at a level below common consciousness. Other postures, which would doubtless have been discouraging at the origin of the modern natural sciences, may not only prove to be more fruitful at a later stage of their development, but also, more widely, favor new syntheses between the search for the “good life” and the search for knowledge. Such alternative postures would substitute confident receptivity for “tense interest” (which, according to Husserl, is what intentionality consists of); they would substitute an ethics of knowing how-to-do and how-to-be for the exclusive value of objective knowledge; they would substitute the willingness to let things deploy themselves, in place of the gestures of grasping and holding fast. They would have as a consequence the acceptance, or indeed the recognition as a saving grace, of the omnipresence of appearance and the cascading deployment of the surface of phenomena.
6 The Zen model: relaxation of sense-making as a way of life
Dôgen, the foremost thinker of Sôtô Zen, offers a particularly pure example of this alternative posture. His writings can be construed as a long hymn to the process of appearing and its realization; a fluctuating process of appearing which calls out to be recognized as what there is, instead of serving as a mere pretext for going beyond it towards the unity of sense-making and the supposed constancy of ultimate being; a process of appearing which in a certain sense remains unperceived, unexpressed, unfathomed (Dôgen, 1231/2007a-2011), and this not because it is inaccessible, but because it is falsely taken as a simple means of access to something else, and because of that it is ignored and passed over in the direction of that “other” which is forever beyond reach; a process of appearing which we often despise as being a simple illusion, but whose neglect only results in what is even more certainly an illusion: that of grasping its foundation by passing through it. “This whole universe”, writes Dôgen, “has nothing hidden (behind the phenomenon)” (1231/2007a-2011). The immanent phenomena have no transcendent meaning. What actually results in a dissimulation is the belief that there is something concealed and, moved by this belief, an inability to stay in place. For it is by going to look elsewhere, by always already transporting oneself towards another place than right here, that one unwittingly masks the actual exhibition of things; whereas it is only in this place, in this “here”, that things show themselves for what they are: as a process of appearing; as a “reflection” of nothing other than a reflection; as a picture of a picture; as an “as if” (Orimo, 2007a). Taking the process of appearing as a disguise amounts to disguising it and to becoming blind to it. Conversely, accepting phenomena as such, with no judgment about their being superficial appearances of something else, realizes the essence of Zen as described by, for example, Suzuki (1940/1996b).
A contrario, what is to be understood is that it is necessary to undertake a long labor, studded with practitionings and fractures of language and concept, to regain a sensitivity to the process of appearing, to make it again our habitat and our element. Once this labor is accomplished, the very word “appearing” becomes useless, out of place, because it still carries with it the very opposition (being versus appearing) from which one is seeking to free oneself. Instead of that, it is suggested that we employ a more neutral vocabulary: the “just as it is” (nyoze in Japanese) (Orimo, 2007b), or the “thusness” (tathatâ in Sanskrit). Thusness is plainly “thus”, in peace and globally meaningless. This vocabulary says nothing, because saying is still meaning something, and meaning something is transporting before and beyond. Instead of projecting, this vocabulary reassembles and gathers in the attention, and then deposits it gently at the point of equilibrium of the presence. This vocabulary knows how to efface itself by means of its own insignificance, in order to allow the budding of a moment which gathers everything into itself, trembling and unstable as the flame in the breath of time. The phrases can then make light of the dualities which erstwhile seemed eternally solidified: form and content, appearance and reality, the reflection and the thing: “Their aspect as such is their nature such as it can be known in the end” (Dôgen, 1231/2007a-2011). The form is the content, the appearance is the reality, the reflection is the thing just as the thing is reflection. The “so it is” is what there is to be known in depth (Dôgen, 1231/2007a-2011), before one lets oneself be captivated by the lure of “the depth of things”, and thereby rendered a stranger to the presence as it is.
7 Applying the Zen model to appease the quantum demand for representational sense-making
Can one imagine a disposition of mind more favorable to a sober and precise interpretation of quantum mechanics? It is, indeed, only by freeing oneself from the transgressive representationalist impulsions, that is, the imperative of scientific realism, that one can at last see this theory for what it is in its daily functioning: a deep knowledge of the surface of things, an optimally coherent systematization of the proce-dures for anticipating appearances, a grammar of experimental information, a historical success of the Kantian strategy which consists of putting to rest one’s metaphysical instincts in order to attain the necessary rules which anticipate the mutual connection of phenomena. It is an optimal approach for making sense of non-sense, rather than a failed attempt at improving representational sense-making.
The whole atmosphere of Dôgenian awakening gives breathing space to epistemological thought, opens up pathways which seemed inaccessible, |77| makes its lines of resistance crumble away, discreetly suggests possibilities which up until then had been discarded. Once brought home to the country of thusness, epistemology is delivered from its inherited rigidities and points of reference, and it discovers lines of reflection which have been not so much unknown as repressed by its history. “This vast sea,” writes Dôgen, “is neither round nor square […]. It is only there where my eye reaches that it appears round for the moment” (1231/2007a-2011). Through the lens of this remark, it is the whole theme of the relativity of phenomena, of their emergence on the occasion of an encounter with an informed vision or a pre-arranged apparatus, that is delivered from skeptical regret and invested with the value of lucidity which governs the practice of Zen. And it is the whole equilibrium of philosophical positions, those which are marginal as well as those which are dominant, the vanquished and the victors, that is decisively shifted to the benefit of a climate which favors a renewed understanding of this theory, which has the reputation of being incomprehensible: quantum mechanics. Indeed, understanding or (with its Latin root) comprehension consists of taking with, taking with us, recognizing as our own. How can we fully assimilate quantum mechanics into our familiar set of bearings if we have not changed what is familiar to the point of integrating in it the delicate shiftings on the surface of things?
Conversely, some of the most singular quantum concepts seem able not only to shed light, but also to formalize (by means of the generalized quantum theory) the state of mind or the way of being-in-the-world that renders them acceptable. Consider that a state of mind which is fully receptive to thusness is “a-categorical”; that it falls short of categories which discriminate and separate, which force an appearance to mean something and thereby distract attention towards the future rather than holding it firmly in the bath of presence. In the generalized quantum theory, the a-categorical state can be formalized by the superposition of state-vectors, or by state-vectors which have not yet been decomposed according to the vector-base of any observable whatsoever. This way of formalizing a state of mind is not just a simple analogy without any repercussions, but a veritable tool for prediction which has been applied with success to psycho-physiological situations such as perceptual bi-stability (Atmanspacher and Fach, 2005).
8 Conclusion
Thus we can witness the installation of the synergy we announced, the two-way enrichment between a way of being which values a floating in thusness, an acceptance of representational non-sense, and a pure physics of the phenomenon; between a way which frees us from the “haunting of meaning (telos)” (Orimo, 2007a) and a scientific theory which blocks all flights of fancy towards the further reaches of elsewhere. The application of quantum theory to context-dependent human decisions does not require any sort of community in the nature of electrons and human beings. In the same way, this synergy between a “Zen-attitude” and quantum epistemology does not suppose the least identity – in terms of historical objectives and domains of validity – between the experience of awakening and laboratory practice. All that it requires is to take due account of what an act of research owes to the value-systems to which the seeker after truth is predisposed, to his cultural restrictions and his acquired openings.
References
Atmanspacher, H., & Fach, W. (2005). Acategoriality as mental instability. Journal ofMind and Behavior, 26, 181-206.
Bell, J. S. (1987). Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Bitbol, M. (1983). An analysis of the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen correlations in terms of events. Physics Letters A, 96(2), 66-70.
Bitbol, M. (1996a). Schrödinger’s Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Bitbol, M. (1996b). Mécanique Quantique: Une Introduction Philosophique. Paris, France: Flammarion.
Bitbol, M. (1998). La mécanique quantique comme théorie des probabilités généralisée. In E. Klein, & Y. Sacquin (Eds), Prévision et Probabilités dans les Sciences, Paris, France: Editions Frontières.
Bitbol, M. (2003). A cure for metaphysical illusions: Kant, quantum mechanics and Madhyamaka. In B. A. Wallace (Ed.), Buddhism & Science: Breaking New Ground (pp. 325-364). New York, NY: Columbia University Press.
Bitbol, M. (2009). Decoherence and the constitution of objectivity. In M. Bitbol, P. Kerszberg, & J. Petitot (Eds), Constituting Objectivity: Transcendental Perspectives on Modern Physics (pp. 347-358). Berlin, Germany: Springer.
Bitbol, M. (Ed.) (2009). Théorie Quantique et Sciences Humaine. Paris, France: CNRS Editions.
Bitbol, M. (2010). De l’Intérieur du Monde: Pour une Philosophie et une Science des Relations. Paris, France: Flammarion.
Bitbol, M. (2011). La théorie quantique et la surface des choses. In Y. Orimo (Ed.), Maitre Dôgen: Shôbôgenzô. La vraie Loi, Trésor de l’Œil: Traduction integrale – Tome 5. Vannes, France: Sully.
Bohm, D. (1984). Wholeness and Implicate Order. London, UK: Ark Paperbacks. Brukner, C., & Zeilinger, A. (2009). Information invariance and quantum prob-abilities. Foundations of Physics, 39, 677-689. |79
Bruza, P., Sofge, D., Lawless, W., van Rijsbergen, K., & Klusch, M. (Eds) (2009a). Quantum Interaction: Third International Symposium, QI 2009. Berlin, Germany: Springer.
Bruza, P. D., Kitto, K., Nelson, D., & McEvoy C. (2009b). Is there something quan-tum-like about the human mental lexicon? Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 53, 362-377.
Capra, F (1975/2010). The Tao of Physics. Boston, MA: Shambhala.
Clark, A. (1997). Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Descola, P. (2008). Par-dela Nature et Culture. Paris, France: Gallimard. Destouches-Février, P. (1951). La Structure des Theories Physiques. Paris, France: Presses Universitaires de France.
Dôgen (1231/2007-2011). Shôbôgenzô. Vannes, France: Sully.
Einstein, A., Podolsky, B., & Rosen, N. (1935/1983). Can quantum-mechanical description of reality be considered complete? In J. A. Wheeler, & W. H. Zurek (Eds), Quantum Theory and Measurement. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Einstein, A. (1989). Oeuvres Choisies 1: Quanta. Paris, France: Seuil.
Elitzur, A. C., & Vaidman, L. (1993). Quantum mechanical interaction-free meas-urements. Foundations of Physics, 23, 987-997.
Elitzur, A. C., Dolev, S., & Zeilinger, A. (2003). Time-reversed EPR and the choice of histories in quantum mechanics. In I. Antoniou, V. A. Sadovnichy, & H. Walther (Eds), The Physics of Communication: Proceedings of the XXII Solvay Conference in Physics (pp. 452-461). Singapore: World Scientific Publishing.
Espagnat, B. d’ (1994). Le Reel Voile. Paris, France: Fayard.
Herrigel, E. (1948/1993). Le Zen dans l’Art Chevaleresque du Tir àl’Arc. _Paris, France: Dervy.
Kant, I. (1770/2004). Kant’s Inaugural Dissertation of 1770. (W. J. Eckoff, Trans.). Whitefish, MT: Kessinger Publishing.
Lévy-Leblond, J. M., & Balibar, F (1984). Quantique: Rudiments. Paris, France: Intereditions.
Lyre, H. (1999). Against measurement? — on the concept of information. In P. Blanchard, & A. Jadczyk (Eds), Quantum Future: From Volta and Como to Present and Beyond (pp. 139-149). Berlin, Germany: Springer.
Lock, G. (1992). Wittgenstein: Philosophie, Logique, Thérapeutique. Paris, France: Presses Universitaires de France.
Orimo, Y. (2007a). Le soi cosmique chez maitre Dôgen et la subjectivite retrouvée. In Dôgen (1231/2007-2011), Shôbôgenzô. Vannes, France: Sully.
Orimo, Y. (2007b). Introduction au Shoho Jisso. In Dôgen (1231/2007-2011), Shôbôgenzô. Vannes, France: Sully.
Scheler, M. (1926/1993). Problèmes de Sociologie de la Connaissance. (S. Mesure, Trans.). Paris, France: Presses Universitaires de France.
Schrödinger, E. (1935/1983). The present situation in quantum mechanics. In J. A. Wheeler, & W. H. Zurek (Eds), Quantum Theory and Measurement. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Schrödinger, E. (1951). Science and Humanism. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Schrödinger, E. (1954). Nature and the Greeks. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Scully, M. 0., & Drühl, K. (1982). Quantum eraser: a proposed photon correlation experiment concerning observation and “delayed choice” in quantum mechanics. Physical Review A, 25(4), 2208-2213.
Seamon, D., & Zajonc, A. (Eds) (1998). Goethe’s Way of Science: A Phenomenology of Nature. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
Smerlak, M., & Rovelli, C. (2007). Relational EPR. Foundations of Physics, 37, 427-445.
Stengers, I. (1997). Cosmopolitiques 4: Mecanique Quantique, la Fin du Nye. Paris, France: La Decouverte.
Suarez, A. (2000). Quantum mechanics versus multisimultaneity in experiments with acousto-optic choice devices. Physics Letters A, 269(5-6), 293-302.
Suzuki, D. T. (1940/1996). Zen Buddhism. New York, NY: Harmony.
Thom, R. (1993). Predire n’est pas Expliquer. Paris, France: Flammarion.
Van Fraassen, B. (2002). The Empirical Stance. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Van Fraassen, B. (2008). Scientific Representations: Paradoxes of Perspective. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Varela, F J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Wheeler, J. A. (1978). The “past” and the “delayed-choice double-slit experiment”. In A. R. Marlow (Ed.), Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Theory (pp. 9-48). New York, NY: Academic Press.
Wittgenstein, L. (1953/1968). Philosophical Investigations. Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell.
Zwirn, H. (2009). Formalisme quantique et preferences indeterminees en theorie de la decision. In M. Bitbol (Ed.), Theorie Quantique et Sciences Humaines. Paris, France: CNRS Editions.
Endnotes
1
A former version of this article, in French, was published in Dôgen (1231 2007-2011). The title of that original version was “La theorie quantique et la surface des choses” (Bitbol, 2011). An English translation prepared by John Stewart formed the basis of the current text.
2
This famous book contains many cases of over-determination and hasty analogies. For example: “Like the mystics, physicists are now approaching the question of non-sensory experience of reality”; “The fundamental unity of the universe is not only the central characteristic of mystical experience, it is also one of the most important revelations of modern physics”; “The emptiness of Eastern mystics can well be compared to the quantum field”; “Physicists and mystics study different aspects of this single reality”, and so on.
3
This (imaginary) machine comprises a fragment of radioactive matter having one chance in two of disintegrating over the time of one hour, and a flask of poison which is released when the disintegration occurs. If the poison is released, it kills the cat.
4
Bell’s theorem establishes the incompatibility of quantum mechanics with certain inequalities (the Bell inequalities) which inevitably result from theories with local hidden variables.
Found a mistake? Contact corrections/at/cepa.infoDownloaded from http://cepa.info/2477 on 2016-05-13 · Publication curated by Alexander Riegler