Volume 5 · Number 1 · Pages 19-39

< Previous Paper · Next Paper >

Cybersemiotic Pragmaticism and Constructivism

Søren Brier

Download the full text in
PDF (524 kB)

Abstract

Context: Radical constructivism claims that we have no final truth criteria for establishing one ontology over another. This leaves us with the question of how we can come to know anything in a viable manner. According to von Glasersfeld, radical constructivism is a theory of knowledge rather than a philosophy of the world in itself because we do not have access to a human-independent world. He considers knowledge as the ordering of experience to cope with situations in a satisfactory way. Problem: Von Foerster and Krippendorff show that the central goal of a constructivist theory of knowing must be to find a way of putting the knower into a known that is constructed so as to keep the knower, as well as the knowing process, viable in practice. Method: The conceptual and philosophical analysis of present theories and their necessary prerequisites suggests that such foundation for viable knowing can be built on the analysis of what the ontological prerequisites are for establishing viable observing, cognition, communication and observer-communicators, and communication media and vehicles. Results: The moment an observer chooses to accept his/her own embodied conscious presence in this world as well as language, he/she must accept other humans as partly independently existing conversation partners; if knowledge and knowing has to make sense, he/she must also accept as prerequisites for our observation and conversation a pre-linguistic reality from which our bodies come and which our conversation is often about. Furthermore, we can no longer claim that there is a reality that we do not know anything about: From being here in conversation, we know that the world can produce more or less stable embodied consciousnesses that can exchange and construct conceptual meanings through embodied conversations and actions that last over time and exist in space-time and mind, and are correlated to our embodied practices. We can also see that our communication works through signs for all living systems as well as in human language, understood as a structured and progressively developed system of communication. The prerequisite for this social semiotic production of meaning is the fourfold “semiotic star of cybersemiotics,” which includes at least four different worlds: our bodies, the combination of society, culture and language, our consciousness, and also an outer nature. Implications: The semiotic star in cybersemiotics claims that the internal subjective, the intersubjective linguistic, our living bodies, and nature are irreducible and equally necessary as epistemological prerequisites for knowing. The viable reality of any of them cannot be denied without self-refuting paradoxes. There is an obvious connectedness between the four worlds, which Peirce called “synechism.” It also points to Peirce’s conclusion that logic and rationality are part of the process of semiosis, and that meaning in the form of semiosis is a fundamental aspect of reality, not just a construction in our heads. Erratum: The paper erroneously refers to “pleroma.” The correct term is “plemora.”

Key words: ontology, embodiment, philosophy of observing, second-order cybernetics, autopoiesis, semiotics, language, phenomenology, radical constructivism, Edmund Husserl, Charles Sanders Peirce, George Spencer-Brown

Citation

Brier S. (2009) Cybersemiotic Pragmaticism and Constructivism. Constructivist Foundations 5(1): 19-39. Available at http://www.univie.ac.at/constructivism/journal/5/1/019.brier

Export article citation data: Plain Text · BibTex · EndNote · Reference Manager (RIS)

References

Atkin A. (2005) C. S. Peirce’s pragmatism. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved from http://www.iep.utm.edu/peircepr/ on 15 October 2009 << Google Scholar

Bateson F. & Bateson M. C. (2005) Angels fear: Towards an epistemology of the sacred. Hampton Press, New Jersey. Originally published in 1987. << Google Scholar

Bateson G. (1973) Steps to an ecology of mind. Paladin, New York. << Google Scholar

Bateson G. (1980) Mind and nature: A necessary unit. Bantam Books, New York. << Google Scholar

Berkeley G. (1948–1957) The works of George Berkeley, bishop of Cloyne. Nine volumes. Edited by A. A. Luce & T. E. Jessop. Thomas Nelson and Sons, London. << Google Scholar

Bhaskar R. A. (1975) A realist theory of science. Version, London. << Google Scholar

Brier S. (2006) Informationsvidenskabsteori. Second edition. Forlaget Samfundslitteratur, Copenhagen. << Google Scholar

Brier S. (2007) Applying Luhmann’s system theory as part of a transdisciplinary frame for communication science. Cybernetics & Human Knowing 14(2–3): 29–65. << Google Scholar

Brier S. (2008) A Peircean panentheist scientific mysticism. International Journal of Transpersonal Studies 27: 20–45. << Google Scholar

Brier S. (2008) Bateson and Peirce on the pattern that connects and the sacred. In: Hoffmeyer J. (ed.) A legacy for living systems: Gregory Bateson as a precursor for biosemiotic thinking. Biosemiotics 2. Springer, London: 229–255. << Google Scholar

Brier S. (2008) Cybersemiotics: Why information is not enough. University of Toronto Press, Toronto. << Google Scholar

Brier S. (2008) The paradigm of Peircean biosemiotics. Signs 2: 30–81. << Google Scholar

Deacon T. W. (1997) The symbolic species. Norton, New York. << Google Scholar

Deely J. (1990) Basics of semiotics. First Edition, Indiana University Press, Indiana. << Google Scholar

Esbjorn-Hargens S. & Zimmerman M. (2009) Integral ecology: Uniting multiple perspectives on the natural world. Integral Books, Boston MA. << Google Scholar

Foerster H. von (1979) The cybernetics of cybernetics. In: Krippendorff K. (ed.) Communication and control in society. Gordon and Breach Science Publishers, New York: 5–8. << Google Scholar

Foerster H. von (1981) On cybernetics of cybernetics of cybernetics and social theory. In: Roth G. & Schwegler H. (eds.) Self-organizing systems, an interdisciplinary approach. Campus, Frankfurt: 102–105. << Google Scholar

Foerster H. von (1984) On self-organizing systems and their environment. In: Observing systems. Intersystems, Seaside CA: 2–23. Originally published in Yovits M. C. & Cameron S. (eds.) (1960) Self-Organizing systems. Pergamon Press, London: 31–50. << Google Scholar

Foerster H. von (2003) Ethics and second-order cybernetics. In: Understanding understanding. Springer, New York: 287–304. Originally published in French in: Ray Y. & Prieur B. (eds.) (1991) Système, ethique, perspectives en therapie familiale. ESF editeur, Paris: 41–55. << Google Scholar

Gadamer H.-G. (1975) Truth and method. Seabury Press, New York. << Google Scholar

Glasersfeld E. von (1991) Distinguishing the observer: An attempt at interpreting Maturana. Retrieved on 28 April 2009 from http://www.oikos.org/vonobserv.htm. << Google Scholar

Glasersfeld E. von (2007) Key works in radical constructivism. Sense Publishers, Rotterdam. << Google Scholar

Guyer P. (1998) Kant, Immanuel. In: Craig E. (ed.) Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy. Routledge, London. Retrieved on October 14, 2009 from http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/DB047SECT5 << Google Scholar

Heidegger M. (1995) The fundamental concepts of metaphysics: World, finitude, solitude. Indiana University Press, Indiana. << Google Scholar

Hintikke J. (1998) What is abduction? The fundamental problem of contemporary epistemology. Transaction of the Charles S. Peirce Society XXXIV (3): 503–534. << Google Scholar

Husserl E. (1931) Ideas: A general introduction to pure phenomenology. Translated by W. R. Boyce Gibson. Humanities Press, New York. Originally published in 1913. << Google Scholar

Husserl E. (1970) Logical investigations. 2 Volumes. Translated by J. N. Findlay. Routledge and Kegan Paul: London. Originally published in 1921. << Google Scholar

Husserl E. (1997) Fænomonologiens idé. Hans Reitzels Forlag, Copenhagen. English translation: (1999) The idea of phenomenology. Husserliana: Edmund Husserl Collected Works Volume 8. Translated by L. Hardy. Kluwer, Dordrecht. << Google Scholar

Husserl E. (1999) Cartesianske meditationer, Hans Reitzels forlag, København. Translated from Husserl E. (1977) Cartesian meditations. Kluwer Academic Publisher, Dordrecht. << Google Scholar

Huxley A. (1945) The perennial philosophy. Chatto & Windus, London. << Google Scholar

Isayeva N. (1993) Shankara and Indian philosophy. Sri Satguru Publications, Delhi. << Google Scholar

John of the Crosss (2003) Dark night of the soul. Dover publications, New York. << Google Scholar

Jung C. G. (1962) Seven sermons to the dead. In: Memories, dreams, reflections. Edited by Aniela Jaffe. Translated by Richard & Clara Winston. Vintage Books, New York. Originally published in 1916. << Google Scholar

Krippendorff K. (1991) Stepping stones towards a constructivist epistemology for mass-communication. Unpublished manuscript prepared for presentation to the annual meeting of the Deutsche Gesellschaft für Publizistik und Kommunikationswissenschaft in Bamberg, Germany, 8–10 May 1991, 32 pages. << Google Scholar

Kuhn T. (1970) The structure of scientific revolutions. Second Edition. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago. << Google Scholar

Lorenz K. (1982) Kant’s doctrine of the a priori in the light of contemporary biology. In: Plotkin H. C. (ed.) Learning, development and culture. John Wiley, Chichester: 121–143. Originally published as: Lorenz K. (1941) Kants Lehre vom Apriorischen im Lichte gegenwärtiger Biologie. Blätter für Deutsche Philosophie 15: 94–125. << Google Scholar

Luhmann N. (1990) Essays on self-reference. Colombia University Press, New York. << Google Scholar

Luhmann N. (1995) Social systems. Stanford University Press, Stanford CA. << Google Scholar

Mach E. (1984) The analysis of sensations and the relation of the physical to the psychical. Translated by C. M. Williams. Open Court, La Salle. Originally published in 1896. << Google Scholar

Maturana H. & Varela F. (1980) Autopoiesis and cognition: The Realization of the Living. Reidel, Dordrecht. << Google Scholar

Maturana H. & Varela F. (1986) Tree of knowledge: Biological roots of human understanding. Shambhala Publishers, London. << Google Scholar

Maturana H. (1981) Autopoiesis. In: Zeleny M. (ed.) Autopoiesis: A theory of living organization. North Holland, New York: 21–30. << Google Scholar

Maturana H. (1983) What is it to see? Archivos de biologia y medicina experimentales 16: 255–269. << Google Scholar

Maturana H. (1988) Reality: The search for objectivity, or the quest for a compelling argument. The Irish Journal of Psychology 9(1): 25–82. << Google Scholar

Maturana H. (2000) The nature of the laws of nature. Yearbook Edition of Systems Research and Behavioral Science, Systems Research 17(5): 459–468. << Google Scholar

Merleau-Ponty M. (2005) Phenomenology of perception. Routledge, London. Originally published in French as: Merleau-Ponty M. (1945) Phenomenologie de la perception. Callimard, Paris. << Google Scholar

Nargajuna (1995) The fundamental wisdom of the middle way. Translated and commented by Jay L. Garfield. Oxford University Press, Oxford. << Google Scholar

Oluffa Pedersen E. & Toft P. (2004) Positivisme: Erfaringsbaseret viden formuleret i en logisk sprogramme. In: Fuglsang L. & Bitsch Olsen P. (eds.) Videnskabsteori i samfundsvidenskaberne. Roskilde Universitetsforlag, Copenhagen: 55–77. << Google Scholar

Peirce C. S. (1994) CP: The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Electronic edition reproducing Past Masters. Hartshorne C. & Weiss P. (eds.) (1931–1935) Vols. I-VI. Harvard University Press, Cambridge; Burks A. (ed.) (1958) Vols. VII–VIII. Harvard University Press, Cambridge. Intelex Corporation, Charlottesville. All quotes refer to Peirce’s Collected Papers (1994) abbreviated as “CP.” << Google Scholar

Popper K. (1972) Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach. The Clarendon Press, Oxford. << Google Scholar

Sharma C. (2009) A critical survey of Indian philosophy. Motilal Banarsidass, Delhi. << Google Scholar

Spencer-Brown G. (1969) Laws of form. Allen and Unwin, London. << Google Scholar

Spencer-Brown G. (1972) Laws of form. Julien Press, New York. << Google Scholar

Spencer-Brown G. (as James Keys) (1974) Only two can play this game. Bantam Books, New York. << Google Scholar

Steuchius Eugubinus A. (1972) De perenni philosophia, Libri X. Paris. Johnson Reprint, New York. Originally published in 1540 in Paris. << Google Scholar

Stjernfelt F. (2007) Diagramatology: An investigation on the borderlines of phenomenology, ontology, and semiotics. Springer, New York. << Google Scholar

Uexküll J. von (1982) The theory of meaning. Semiotica 42(1): 25–82. Originally published in 1940. << Google Scholar

Wittgenstein L. (2001) Philosophical investigations. Blackwell Publishing, Oxford. Originally published in 1953. << Google Scholar

Zahavi D. (2001) Husserl and transcendental intersubjectivity. Ohio University Press, Ohio. << Google Scholar

Zahavi D. (2002) Husserl’s phenomenology. Stanford University Press, Stanford. << Google Scholar