Volume 11 · Number 2 · Pages 346–353

< Previous Paper · Next Paper >

Never Mind the Gap: Neurophenomenology, Radical Enactivism, and the Hard Problem of Consciousness

Michael D. Kirchhoff & Daniel D. Hutto

Download the full text in
PDF (1427 kB)

> Citation > Similar > References > Add Comment

Abstract

Context: Neurophenomenology, as formulated by Varela, offers an approach to the science of consciousness that seeks to get beyond the hard problem of consciousness. There is much to admire in the practical approach to the science of consciousness that neurophenomenology advocates. Problem: Even so, this article argues, the metaphysical commitments of the enterprise require a firmer foundation. The root problem is that neurophenomenology, as classically formulated by Varela, endorses a form of non-reductionism that, despite its ambitions, assumes rather than dissolves the hard problem of consciousness. We expose that neurophenomenology is not a natural solution to that problem. We defend the view that whatever else neurophenomenology might achieve, it cannot close the gap between the phenomenal and the physical if there is no such gap to close. Method: Building on radical enactive and embodied approaches to cognitive science that deny that the phenomenal and the physical are metaphysically distinct, this article shows that the only way to deal properly with the hard problem is by denying the metaphysical distinction between the physical and the phenomenal that gives the hard problem life. Results: This article concludes by discussing how neurophenomenology might be reformulated under the auspices of a radically enactive and embodied account of cognition. That is, only by denying that there are two distinct phenomena - the physical and the phenomenal - can the neurophenomenological project get on with addressing its pragmatic problems of showing how neuroscientists may be guided by first-person data in their analysis of third-person experimental data, and vice versa. Implications: The topic addressed in this article is of direct value to consciousness studies in general and specifically for the project of neurophenomenology. If the neurophenomenological project is to deal with the hard problem, it must denude itself of its non-reductionist background assumption and embrace a strict identity thesis. Constructivist content: Radical enactive and embodied approaches to mind and consciousness adopt a view of consciousness as a dynamic activity - something an organism enacts in ongoing engagement with its environment. These approaches therefore share with constructivist approaches an action-based view of mind.

Key words: Consciousness, radical enactivism, neurophenomenology, hard problem of consciousness.

Citation

Kirchhoff M. D. & Hutto D. D. (2016) Never mind the gap: Neurophenomenology, radical enactivism, and the hard problem of consciousness. Constructivist Foundations 11(2): 346–353. http://constructivist.info/11/2/346

Export article citation data: Plain Text · BibTex · EndNote · Reference Manager (RIS)

Similar articles

Solomonova E. & Sha X. W. (2016) Exploring the Depth of Dream Experience: The Enactive Framework and Methods for Neurophenomenological Research

Hawes R. (2013) Art & Neurophenomenology: Putting the Experience Before the Words

Vörös S. & Bitbol M. (2017) Enacting Enaction: A Dialectic Between Knowing and Being

Froese T., Gould C. & Barrett A. (2011) Re-Viewing from Within: A Commentary on First- and Second-Person Methods in the Science of Consciousness

Gasparyan D. (2016) Consciousness as Self-Description in Differences

References

Barandiaran X. E. & Di Paolo E. A. (2014) A genealogical map of the concept of habit. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8: 522. << Google Scholar

Barandiaran X. E., Di Paolo E. & Rohde M. (2009) Defining agency: Individuality, normativity, asymmetry, and spatio-temporality in action. Adaptive Behavior 17(5): 367–386. Available at http://cepa.info/324

Bayne T. (2004) Closing the gap? Some questions for neurophenomenology. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 3: 349–364. Available at http://cepa.info/2260

Beaton M. (2009) An analysis of qualitative feel as the introspectible subjective aspect of a space of reasons. D.Phil. thesis. University of Sussex, Brighton. << Google Scholar

Beaton M. (2009) Qualia and introspection. Journal of Consciousness Studies 16: 88–110. << Google Scholar

Beaton M. (2013) Phenomenology and embodied action. Constructivist Foundations 8(3): 298–313. Available at http://constructivist.info/8/3/298

Bitbol M. (2012) Neurophenomenology, an ongoing practice of/in consciousness. Constructivist Foundations 7(3): 165–173. Available at http://constructivist.info/7/3/165

Bruineberg J. & Rietveld E. (2014) Self-organization, free energy minimization, and optimal grip on a field of affordances. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8: 599. << Google Scholar

Chalmers D. (1996) The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press, New York. << Google Scholar

Chalmers D. (2002) Consciousness and its place in nature. In: Chalmers D. (ed.) Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings. Oxford University Press, Oxford: 247–272. << Google Scholar

Chalmers D. J. (1995) Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of consciousness studies 2(3): 200–219. << Google Scholar

Chemero A. (2009) Radical embodied cognitive science. MIT Press, Cambridge MA. << Google Scholar

Clark A. (2003) Natural-born cyborgs: Minds, technologies, and the future of human intelligence. Oxford University Press, Oxford. << Google Scholar

Craver C. F. & Bechtel W. (2007) Top-down causation without top-down causes. Biology & Philosophy 22(4): 547–563. << Google Scholar

Depraz N. (2013) An experiential phenomenology of novelty: The dynamic antinomy of attention and surprise. Constructivist Foundations 8(3): 280–287. Available at http://constructivist.info/8/3/280

Depraz N., Varela F. J. & Vermersch P. (2004) On becoming aware: A pragmatics of experiencing. John Benjamins, Philadelphia. << Google Scholar

Descola P. (2013) Beyond nature and culture. University of Chicago Press, Chicago. << Google Scholar

Di Paolo E. (2009) Extended Life. Topoi 28: 9–21. Available at http://cepa.info/322

Flanagan O. (1992) Consciousness reconsidered. MIT Press, Cambridge MA. << Google Scholar

Flanagan O. (1993) Consciousness reconsidered. MIT Press, Cambridge MA. << Google Scholar

Foerster H. von (2003) On constructing a reality. In: Foerster H. von, Understanding understanding: Essays on cybernetics and cognition. Springer, New York: 211–227. Originally published in 1973. Available at http://cepa.info/1278

Froese T. & Di Paolo E. A. (2011) The enactive approach: Theoretical sketches from cell to society. Pragmatics & Cognition 19(1): 1–36. Available at http://cepa.info/2367

Froese T. (2014) Review of “Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content” by Daniel D. Hutto and Erik Myin. The Journal of Mind and Behavior 35(1–2): 71–82. Available at http://cepa.info/2273

Froese T., Gould C. & Barrett A. (2011) Re-viewing from within: A commentary on first-and second-person methods in the science of consciousness. Constructivist Foundations 6(2): 254–269. Available at http://constructivist.info/6/2/254

Gallagher S. & Zahavi D. (2008) The phenomenological mind. Routledge, London. << Google Scholar

Gallagher S. (2005) How the body shapes the mind. Claredon Press, Oxford. << Google Scholar

Gallagher S. (2007) Neurophilosophy and neurophenomenology. In: Embree L. & Nenon T. (eds.) Phenomenology 2005. Volume 5. Zeta Press, Bucharest: 293–316. Available at http://cepa.info/2474

Gallagher S. (2012) Phenomenology. Palgrave Macmillan, London. << Google Scholar

Gallagher S., Hutto D. D., Slaby J. & Cole J. (2013) The brain as part of an enactive system. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36(4): 241–422. Available at http://cepa.info/2510

Gallagher S., Reinerman-Jones L., Janz B., Bockelman P. & Trempler J. (2015) A neurophenomenology of awe and wonder. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke UK. << Google Scholar

Gibson J. J. (1979) The ecological approach to visual perception. Houghton-Mifflin, Boston MA. << Google Scholar

González X. (2013) La auto-producción de la subjetividad: autopoiesis y cognición corporizada de alto nivel [The self-production of subjectivity: Autopoiesis and high-level cognition]. In: Razeto P. & Ramos R. (2013) Autopoiesis un concepto vivo. Colección ciencias estructurales. Universitas Nueva civilización, Santiago: 95–118. << Google Scholar

González X. (2014) Emergent novelties: A naturalistic proposal to motor learning. Metatheoria 5(1):18–34. << Google Scholar

Hegel G. W. F. (1977) Phenomenology of spirit. Translated by A. V. Miller with analysis of the text and foreword by J. N. Findlay. Clarendon Press, Oxford. << Google Scholar

Hutto D. D. & Myin E. (2013) Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. MIT Press, Cambridge MA. << Google Scholar

Hutto D. D. (2000) Beyond physicalism. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. << Google Scholar

Hutto D. D. (2015) Overly enactive imagination? Radically re-imagining imagination. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 53: 68–89. << Google Scholar

Hutto D. D., Kirchhoff M. D. & Myin E. (2014) Extensive enactivism: Why keep it all in? Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8: 706. Available at http://cepa.info/2392

Jackson F. (1982) Epiphenomenal qualia. Philosophical Quarterly 32: 127–136. << Google Scholar

Kelso S. (1995) Dynamic patterns. MIT Press, Cambridge MA. << Google Scholar

Kirchhoff M. D. (2015) Experiential fantasies, prediction, and enactive minds. Journal of Consciousness Studies 22(3–4): 68–92. << Google Scholar

Kirchhoff M. D. (2015) Extended cognition & the causal-constitutive fallacy: In search for a diachronic and dynamical conception of constitution. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 90(2): 320–360. << Google Scholar

Lloyd D. (1989) Simple minds. MIT Press, Cambridge MA. << Google Scholar

Luhmann N. (1990): Essays on self-reference. Columbia University Press, New York. << Google Scholar

Lutz A. & Thompson E. (2003) Neurophenomenology: Integrating subjective experience and brain dynamics in the neuroscience of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 10(9–10): 31–52. Available at http://cepa.info/2363

Lutz A. (2002) Toward a neurophenomenology of generative passages: A first empirical case study. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1: 133–167. Available at http://cepa.info/2398

Lutz A., Lachaux J.-P., Martinerie J. & Varela F. J. (2002) Guiding the study of brain dynamics by using first-person data: Synchrony patterns correlate with ongoing conscious states during a simple visual task. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 99: 1586–1591. Available at http://cepa.info/2092

Marbach E. (1993) Mental representation and consciousness: Towards a phenomenological theory of representation and reference. Kluwer, Dordrecht. << Google Scholar

Maturana H. R. & Varela F. F. (1980) Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the living. Reidel, Dordecht. << Google Scholar

Merleau-Ponty M. (1962) Phenomenology of perception. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London. Originally published in French as Merleau-Ponty M. (1945) Phénoménologie de la perception. Callimard, Paris. << Google Scholar

Merleau-Ponty M. (1964) The structure of behavior. Translated by A. L. Fisher. Beacon Press, Boston. << Google Scholar

Moore G. E. (1903) The refutation of idealism. Mind 12(48): 433–453. << Google Scholar

Nagel T. (1974) What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review 83: 435–450. Available at http://cepa.info/2399

Nagel T. (1979) Mortal Questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. << Google Scholar

Nisbett R. E. & Wilson T. D. (1977) Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review 84: 231–259. << Google Scholar

Noë A. (2004) Action in perception. MIT Press, Cambridge MA. << Google Scholar

Noë A. (2012) Varieties of presence. Harvard University Press, Cambridge MA. << Google Scholar

O’Regan J. K., Myin E. & Noë A. (2006) Skill, corporality and alerting capacity in an account of sensory consciousness. In: Laureys S. (ed.) Boundaries of consciousness. Elsevier, Amsterdam: 55–68. << Google Scholar

Papineau D. (2002) Thinking about consciousness. Clarendon Press, Oxford. << Google Scholar

Petitmengin C. & Lachaux J. P. (2013) Microcognitive science: Bridging experiential and neuronal microdynamics. Frontier in Human Neurosciience 7: 617. Available at http://cepa.info/934

Petitmengin C., Remillieux A., Cahour B. & Carter-Thomas S. (2013) A gap in Nisbett and Wilson’s findings? A first-person access to our cognitive process. Consciousness and Cognition 22(2): 654–669. Available at http://cepa.info/931

Raab T. & Eder T. (2015) Selbstbeobachtung: Oswald Wieners Denkpsychologie. Suhrkamp, Berlin. << Google Scholar

Rössler O. E. (1998) Endophysics: The world as an interface. World Scientific, Singapore. << Google Scholar

Rossmanith N. & Reddy V. (2016) Structure and openness in the development of self in infancy. Journal of Consciousness Studies 23(1–2): 237–257. << Google Scholar

Roy J.-M., Petitot J., Pachoud B. & Varela F. J. (1999) Beyond the gap: An introduction to naturalizing phenomenology. In: Petitot J., Varela F. J., Pachoud B. & Roy J.-M. (eds.) Naturalizing phenomenology. Stanford University Press, Stanford CA: 1–80. << Google Scholar

Searle J. (1992) The rediscovery of the mind. MIT Press, Cambridge MA. << Google Scholar

Shoemaker S. (1996) The first-person perspective and other essays. Cambridge University Press, New York NY. << Google Scholar

Silberstein M. & Chemero A. (2012) Complexity and extended phenomenological-cognitive systems. Topics in Cognitive Science 4(1): 35–50. Available at http://cepa.info/2400

Silberstein M. & Chemero A. (2015) Extending neutral monism to the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies 22(3–4): 181–194. << Google Scholar

Thompson E. & Stapleton M. (2009) Making sense of sense-making: Reflections on enactive and extended mind theories. Topoi 28(1): 23–30. Available at http://cepa.info/2290

Thompson E. & Varela F. J. (2001) Radical embodiment. Neural dynamics and consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 5(10): 418–445. Available at http://cepa.info/2085

Thompson E. (2004) Life and mind: From autopoiesis to neurophenomenology. A tribute to Francisco Varela. Phenomenology and the cognitive Sciences 3(4): 381–398. Available at http://cepa.info/1137

Thompson E. (2007) Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Harvard University Press, Cambridge MA. << Google Scholar

Uexküll J. von (1921) Umwelt und Innenwelt der Tiere. Second edition. Julius Springer, Berlin. Available at http://cepa.info/2404

Varela F. J. (1976) Not one, not two. CoEvolution Quarterly 12(1): 62–67. Available at http://cepa.info/2055

Varela F. J. (1992) Autopoiesis and a biology of intentionality. In: McMullin B. (ed.) Proceedings of a workshop on “Autopoiesis and Perception.” Dublin City University, Dublin: 4–14. Available at http://cepa.info/1274

Varela F. J. (1996) Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy for the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies 3(4): 330–349. Available at http://cepa.info/1893

Varela F. J. (1999) The specious present: The neurophenomenology of time consciousness. In: Petitot J., Varela F. J., Pachoud B. & Roy J. M. (eds.) Naturalizing phenomenology. Stanford University Press, Stanford CA: 266–314. Available at http://cepa.info/2081

Varela F. J., Thompson E. & Rosch E. (1991) The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. MIT Press, Cambridge MA. << Google Scholar

Vörös S. (2014) The Uroboros of Consciousness: Between the Naturalisation of Phenomenology and the Phenomenologisation of Nature. Constructivist Foundations 10(1): 96–104. Available at http://cepa.info/1173

Velmans M. (2009) Understanding consciousness. Second edition. Routledge, London. << Google Scholar

Weber A. & Varela F. J. (2002) Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the cognitive sciences 1(2): 97–125. Available at http://cepa.info/2087

Zahavi D. (2003) Intentionality and phenomenality: A phenomenological take on the hard problem. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 29(Supplement): 63–92. << Google Scholar

Zahavi D. (2013) Naturalized phenomenology: A desideratum or a category mistake? Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 72: 23–42. << Google Scholar

Comments: 0

To stay informed about comments to this publication and post comments yourself, please log in first.